Throughout reading Wilson’s On Human Nature, I have been persistently bothered by the
implications that such reductionist approaches have upon, among other things,
our concept of free will. This debate, of course, is philosophically ancient,
but nevertheless extremely relevant. Many contemporary cultures, as well as
many notions of patriotism, are based around the concept of freedom (which
admittedly is a bit murkier and more political than ‘free will’), and perceived
threats to such freedom have led to great social change: hundreds of
revolutions and rebellions that have shaped the way our earth is today. Would
this continue, i.e. would we have rebellions such as the Arab Spring or the
Occupy movement if we were made intensely aware that these rebellions contribute
to a repetitive cycle of power changing hands, of political and economic
measurements of entropy? My guess would be, probably not, no. For as much as it
is within human nature to maintain the status quo, we are often made
uncomfortable when we come to realize that someone/thing else is pulling the
strings, or that we are in any such way predicable (this occurs on both an
individual and group-oriented level (note: predictable = insult; reliable =
compliment, even though there is an extreme overlap in definition )).
Butler hashes this all out pretty extensively in Lilith’s Brood. Through her employment
of the Oankali, she sets up seriously interesting sociological, perhaps even
sociobiological, experiments within her text. The Oankali can be seen as
representing figures such as Wilson, although they are less of what Wilson is and more of which he aspires to be or
at the very least, the future that interests him profoundly. Take, as a quick
example, what the cohort of humans do in the training floor. The Oankali’s
simulation of a terrestrial forest is so complete and thorough that many of the
subjects believe it not to be a simulation, but in fact, Earth itself. Their
response, then, is to split. They leave their camp, in which are supplies and
tools, and medicinal advances far beyond their comprehension (oolio healing
powers) because their autonomy is threatened. Lilith is apprehensive towards ‘exploring,’
partially because she wants not to abandon Nikanj, but also because she knows
the oolio have anticipated it, and therefore she views it as a futile action,
one that will in no way demonstrate free will (at least until she is seduced by
the small possibility that they could actually be on Earth). Lilith’s knowledge
of the oolio’s anticipation of the human’s reaction is the very type of
transcendental moment that Wilson, in his most benevolent, hopes to obtain
within humanity through the study of sociobiology: a shift in our tendencies
through a better understanding and acknowledgment of those very tendencies (NB:
also a cornerstone in just about any type of contemporary psychological
therapy).
The text, then, represents a highly fictionalized account of
Wilson and his contemporaries against the general public perception of what
Wilson would like to see done with the knowledge obtained through
sociobiological studies. The Oankali are the ultimate sociobiologists: they are
better anthropologists than we could ever aspire to be, as they are able to
study us from outside of our cultural framework, a feat any human could never achieve.
Not only are they experts on human culture, but they have also studied human
beings on the molecular level up on through histology and physiology. Not to
mention their apparent depth of insight with the human psyche. They believe
that they can make improvements to the human species, and they do, without
consent. The humans in the text play themselves. They are largely reactionary
towards the structure and plans of the Oankali and serve as a counterpoint to
the Oankalian (sociobiological) ideology. The main clashes between the two
groups happen within the context of free will.
Which boils down to roughly this: the Oankali do not
recognize human value for free will, or
the perception thereof. I myself do not know whether or not I operate
within free-will or my actions are determined by large (or small) unknown
forces. What I am completely sure of is that I operate under the complete perception of free-will and, to me, that
works just as well. In his chapter on Emergence, Wilson argues that it is
probable, although not within the current constraints of human intelligence, to
predict the future of a human being “with an accuracy exceeding pure chance”
(Wilson, pg 73, actually referring to honeybees, but he makes the humanoid
comparison in the very next paragraph). His concept is that the honey bee,
within the constraints of its particular CNS, has the perception of free-will,
although it is possible for humans, whom arguable have a larger, more aware and
intuitive CNS, to see that the honey bee is simply responding to external
stimuli in an extremely predictable manner. Wilson then postulates that what
humans are able to do to honey bees, in terms of fatalist reduction, could
theoretically be done to us “[b]ut only [with] techniques beyond our present
imagining could [we] hope to achieve even the short-term prediction of the
detailed behavior of an individual human being, and such an accomplishment might
be beyond the capacity of any conceivable intelligence” (Wilson, pg 73).
Octavia Butler has conceived, at least figuratively, of such intelligence
within the Oankali. She is less concerned with the allegorical human study of
the honey bee than she is with what the honey bee feels when we present it with
our prescient data (it also may be worthwhile to mention that to do this, we
would have to figure out a way to make the data digestible to a honey bee,
which cannot read scientific papers or graphs, and this may be even more
difficult than the initial prediction). For free-will and the perception of
free will are functionally identical. The Oankali view their deconstruction of
human choice as Enlightenment, although it is highly detrimental to many of the
human subjects. This is probably best illustrated within the abstract alien sex
between Joseph and Nikanj, when Nikanj is seducing Joseph:
“He
pulled his arm free ‘You said I could choose. I’ve made my choice!’
“You
have, yes…you see. Your body has made a different choice” (Butler 189).
As the Oankali are hyperaware of the way in which humans
function - their predictable responses to external stimuli - they are able to
see ‘past’ choice. What is interesting about the Butler’s text however, is the
moment when the honey bee/human relationship between Oankali and humans breaks
down, when the informatics the Oankali have gathered and applied to humans
fails them in unanticipated ways: when Joseph is murdered. Nikanj admits, when referring
to the murder, that “what happened was … totally unplanned” (Butler 224). This
murder symbolizes the hope that human behavior cannot actually be reduced into
any sort of computational statistics and is perhaps the strongest moment within
the text (thus far) in which Butler seems to disagree with sociobiology.
Furthermore, it is important to note what the Oankali do with Curt, whom surprised
them by being wholly unpredictable: they return him back to suspended
animation, and remove him from the ‘experiment,’ which is much akin to
scientists occluding negative results when presenting their findings.
Butler seems as deeply bothered by Wilson’s claims as I have
been and she uses her text to illustrate how such applications – genetic engineering,
and so forth – can severely threaten either our free will or at the very least,
our perception of free will. She also presents us with a single moment in which
the Oankali are not able to predict human behavior or influence the outcome of
the future, leading us to believe that perhaps Wilson’s theories are more than
just frightening, perhaps they are wrong.
Butler, Octavia E. Lilith’s
Brood. New York City: Grand Central Publishing, 1989
Wilson, Edward O. On Human Nature. Cambridge (Mass.):
Harvard University Press, 2004
This is interesting in many ways, and on many levels. One critical component to this essay working well is your careful acknowledgement that what we certainly have is the perception of free will - we don't know whether we have the actual thing. This is important because you are clearly wrestling with the problem that Wilson (or what he represents, perhaps) poses a serious challenge to many of our aspirations and preconceptions - and yet, those aspirations and preconceptions are themselves very real.
ReplyDeleteThe above is only really meant as a summary of my very positive response to the essay. While remaining somewhat too general for somewhat too long, you pull of a reading of both Butler and Wilson which is alive to their nuances - you have a great sense of Butler's complex unease, and of the fact that Wilson believes that all knowledge, including this knowledge (assuming he is correct) is liberating, when properly applied.
But all of that is just an introduction. If you revise, how to go about it?
What stands out to me most here is an insight that I've certainly never had or read: that Curt (like Cain?) represents freedom, just as he would want to. It's an important insight, and it raises at least two questions for me which could be the basis of a lengthly revision.
1) Is Curt's will-to-freedom, with all of its consequences, something we should celebrate? In other words, should we continue to value autonomy if this is what autonomy looks like? Either way, you have the basis for a lengthier exploration of either Butler or Wilson - or a chance to go off in another direction entirely.
2) How does this insight that Curt=Freedom or autonomy in some sense impact our reading of the 2nd and 3rd books? One might focus on human resisters, or on Akin himself, as a way of moving this discussion forward.