What is immediately obvious in Moby-Dick is that
Melville has done a very thorough job when it comes to describing the whale.
This completely exhaustive exploration of the whales’ insides, outsides and
abstractions mirrors the complete fervor with which Ahab hunts the whale: all
in all, Melville is mimicking or feigning monomania in a book that deals
largely with monomania. With all of his talk regarding religion, Melville’s
narrator (which I will refuse to call Ishmael, despite the text’s initial
urging) seems to have found his own religion within the whale itself, more
broadly, within the sciences. Indeed, the narrator has long descriptions of,
among other things, whale biology, whale anthropology, whale psychology, whale
phrenology (!), whale physiognomy,
whale ecology, etc. Through the lens of the whale, Melville touches upon nearly
every science that existed at the time (with obvious exceptions – not even
Melville could make whale chemistry sexy). What results, and what is germane,
is he provides a relatively complete list of the ways in which a whale, or
subject, could be depicted.
“But, as in his narrow-flowing
monomania, not one jot of Ahab’s broad madness had been left behind; so in that
broad madness, not one jot of his great natural intellect had perished”
(Melville, 201). This quote appears, quite appropriately, in the Chapter from
which the title of Melville’s work is derived: Moby-Dick. Famously, Captain Ahab has only one agenda, to capture
the white whale that took away his leg several voyages ago. This monomania is
extensively flushed out throughout Melville’s work: in fact, the entire plot
hinges upon Ahab’s ridiculousness. Indeed, the phrase ‘white whale’ has entered
into our vocabulary (at least I’ve heard several individuals employ it) as
something that a person is obsessed with to a sometimes destructive degree. The
work has a monomaniacal character essential to the plot and also a narrator
whom treats the subject of monomania with equal fervor. If Melville the writer
exists in any of his characters, it is not Ishmael, it is certainly Ahab.
Regardless of all of the criticizing of monomania throughout Moby-Dick, the novel suffers heavily
from its own lengthy digressions concerning the science of the whale.
What is at work here is a problem of
description or representation. Whether or not Melville meant to purposefully
explore this idea in Moby-Dick, the
narrator has profound difficulties in describing the whale, or whaling, in a
way that he finds sufficient. What he does is offer the best he can – a slew of
depictions of whales through just about any major line of inquiry that existed
at the time. What furthers this is smaller, less non-fictiony representations
of whale throughout Moby-Dick which
extend beyond the form of literature
(in ways). The very last extract is that of Whale
Song, a musical description. Within the first few chapters we have a
soliloquy on a painting of a whale, itself a description of whale through
visual art. I don’t doubt there exist more. Melville’s own monomania concerns
his knowledge of a whale. He does not want to kill a whale, nor capitalize (at
least directly) on the whale, but he constantly obsesses over his ability to describe the whale.
It is perhaps important here to
highlight the fact that I am periodically blurring the distinction between the
concepts of knowledge, that is, epistemology, and description or depiction
(mimesis), which is an outward projection of that knowledge. What is troubling,
daunting, and exciting about Moby-Dick
is not only that it constantly switches between the historically contrasted
diegesis (the narrative itself) and the mimesis of the whale and the whaling
industry, but that it so often conflates them. The conflation arises in how
exhaustive the mimesis attempts to be: Melville asserts himself as an authority
on the subject, and arguably has gathered the appropriate knowledge available
in his time to appropriate such a title, yet the general obsession of the
mimesis mirrors and contributes to the concept of monomania which is firmly
anchored within the diegetic portion of the novel. Although the novel is
certainly engaged with the question of whether or not a full knowledge of whale
(or anything) can actually be achieved, it further complicates this by asking
the subsequent question of, if such knowledge is obtainable, can it be properly
described?
The whale was in 1851, as it still
is today, a fantastic subject/object through which to ask these questions. The
majority of individuals are fairly infrequently exposed to the actuality of a
whale, its habitat being far removed from our own. Had Melville chosen a pedestrian
subject that any reader could experience daily, Melville’s plight would have
been diminished, it is the otherness of the whale that makes it a fascinating
subject (to both the narrator and the reader). Yet, assuming that many readers
have not experienced a whale, Moby-Dick yearns to substitute for that
direct experience.
Largely, this is an argument for science’s
or art’s failure to fully understand or represent a subject. Yet it is perhaps
also a comment on the faultiness of science/art’s claim that it indeed can fully understand/represent a
subject. Through his employment of various disciplines towards the whale, many
of which claim to describe the whole through an analysis of the parts (both
material and abstract), Melville illustrates the inherent impossibility of
mimesis.
Much of Aristotle’s theory of
knowledge rests upon his ‘four causes’ of an object (Metaphysics) and his analysis of our construction of knowledge is a
particularly adept lens for examining Moby-Dick.
Aristotle’s first two causes are the material cause and the formal cause.
Within the whale, the material cause would be what the whale is physically made
of, which Melville writes of extensively, e.g. baleen, spermaceti, various
forms of blubber, etc. The second cause is the arrangement of these things,
which Melville highlights as well: the shape and form of the whale
(particularly its head). The last cause is the final cause, which is its
purpose or aim. For the narrator, this cause is strongly tied to economics, for
Ahab, it is violence, and for Melville himself, it is the subject of his work
(quite a purpose). The narrator struggles with the third cause. Aristotle’s
third cause is the efficient cause, which is roughly an object’s source.
Clearly the source of any whale is its respective parental whale, although
clearly Melville thinks this to be insufficient. The real efficient cause of
the whale, for many a devout reader in Melville’s day would clearly be God.
Which raises an important point regarding Ahab’s world view versus the narrator’s,
especially concerning the whale.
For the narrator, the whale’s
causes, and therefore the proper knowledge of the whale exist within science,
that is, they are heavily grounded within the material and the formal cause.
The efficient cause is perhaps hinted at, but is far underdeveloped when
compared to the first two causes. Ahab, on the other hand, focuses entirely on
the third cause. He believes the whale to be either an agent of God or the
Devil (either or – recall class discussion) and openly shows disdain for the
first two causes of the whale. Starbuck, although somewhat tertiary in this
regard, focuses primarily on the final
cause of the whale: the economic potential. Through these characters Melville,
not the narrator, actually presents all four of Aristotle’s causes when it
comes to the whale. However, the effect of this seems not at all demystifying.
What is important, perhaps, is that
Melville illustrates each of these causes within different characters. Not any
one character shows a breadth of understanding of each of the four causes of
the whale, and many show not one. Melville is perhaps critiquing Aristotle’s
theory of causes throughout Moby-Dick,
showing that a thorough understanding of a thing’s material causes by an individual is often entirely contradictory to
that individual’s through understanding of a thing’s efficient causes. It is important that Melville’s work arose during
a time of great scientific revolution, namely Darwin’s theory of evolution
which appeared, basically, to form a bridge between the first/second and third
causes and perhaps Moby-Dick serves
as either a prescient example of the scientific positivism that was already
somewhat underway during the period in which he was writing (or maybe he was
critiquing it – sometimes it’s hard to tell with Melville).
This leads to the observation that
the reader themselves are left to guess or grasp at the final causes of the
whale. Indeed several are offered: Starbuck’s economic cause, the quelling of
Ishmael’s ennui, Ahab’s persistence through his own life and beacon through
navigating his handicap, yet each are given and, at the end of the book
disproved. For the reader is completely imbued with descriptions of the first
three causes of the whale, through endless monologues and soliloquies, yet the
final cause of the whale with regards to the reader is hardly hinted at. Why,
exactly, is the reader given such long-winded descriptions? To what purpose
does their understanding serve the reader, if it does at all? Ishmael wants to
describe the profession of whaling as contrary to the popular belief of the
time that it was “a rather unpoetic and disreputable pursuit” (Melville, 118).
The long digressive moments in the book are the narrator struggling to bring
the rigidity of scientific study to bolster the profession of whaling. If it
is, as I believe, entirely necessary to separate the narrator from Ishmael,
perhaps this is the most concrete manner in which to do it: Ishmael is present
in the boat and views the whale, quite passively and objectively, as that which
the pursuit of which will clear Ishmael’s eyes at the mast-head and improve his
mood, whereas the final cause of the whale for the narrator is a channel for
the interjection of science into a profession he holds dearly and sees as in
need of serious P.R.
The reader, while understanding
these final causes through the perception of the novel’s characters, is forced
to consider what the final cause of the whale may be according to her. A great deal of whale-studying is
arguably performed when Moby-Dick is
read, yet Marine Biologists do not turn to the text for reference in any
serious way (at least in the modern age). From a literary standpoint, the
causes of the literary whale (particularly Moby-Dick himself) can be structured
within the process of writing and the subsequent perception of the reader. If
it can be argued that to fully understand or have knowledge of the whale, we
must understand each of its four causes, the same must be said for Moby-Dick,
and therefore Moby-Dick. The material cause is the writing process
itself. The reader has a flickering perception of original process throughout
the book, as Melville continuously and neurotically analyzes his own sections and
provides insight into motive and intertextuality moments explicitly within the Extracts section and more sporadically
throughout the novel. This is what the literary whale Moby-Dick is constructed
of: Melville’s experiences, beliefs, etc. The formal cause is the
arrangement and pattern of this knowledge and thoughts: precisely the structure
or form of the novel. Word choice, syntax, all of the high-school grammatical
analysis terms one can conjure perform the function of the formal cause of the literary whale. Here too, is where the
scientific descriptions of the whale
come into play: they are all, if divorced from their more theoretical purpose,
descriptive techniques meant, sometimes, to provide the reader with
concretizing details of the whale: Melville for all purposes arranging his
knowledge.
I will here only briefly skim over
defining the efficient cause of the
literary whale, i.e. where it comes from or arises from. I partially avoid this
because such analysis would mostly culminate in the garden-variety lit-crit hermeneutical
tautology, bouncing meaning (and therefore source) of the text between reader,
writer, and document. The only thing, hardly worth mentioning here, is that the
publisher that manufactures the reader’s specific copy could be seen to
contribute to this, or at least could be frivolously considered among other efficient causes.
Which brings us to the final cause of the literary whale. My
argument here, for I do have one, is that the final cause of the whale is essentially identical for all nearly
all characters within the novel and
the reader. This final cause is teleological in its essence: the whale provides
an end. While the economic,
spiritual, and vengeful final purposes of
the whale serve as fine final causes,
they seem absolutely subservient to the teleological purpose of the whale
within the literary framework; thus, both the reader and the characters arrive
at a full understanding (knowledge) of the whale: the whale as end. Both the narrator and Melville seem
keenly aware of this: “I do not know where I can find a better place than just
here, to make mention of one or two other things which to me seem important, as
in printed form establishing the reasonableness of the whole story of the White
Whale, more especially the catastrophe” (Melville, 223). The descriptions and
lectures seem infinitely more purposeful when viewed through the lens of
teleology: they are nuanced depictions of the
agent of change within the work. Not only does the whale reveal its final cause to be that of killing
nearly all characters within the book, it in turn writes the final causes of
those characters: to be killed by Moby-Dick and bolster and continue the
legacy. For the reader, the final cause of the whale exists in the same way;
the whale serves to end the book, in a way that would teeter upon deus-ex-machina if there weren’t such
atheistic threads throughout the preceding narrative.
Regardless, Melville presents the
whale as known – when in fact the reader is left with a great sense of
not-knowing of the whale (although certainly a great sense of knowing a whale) – everything that comes with an
actual physical encounter is present within the novel, yet the actual, physical
encounter itself is inherently absent for the reader, presenting an odd and
entirely uncomfortable form of knowledge.
Melville, Herman. Moby Dick
or, The Whale. 1851. New York : Penguin Books, 2003.
Aristotle. Aristotle in 23 Volumes,
Vols.17, 18, translated by Hugh Tredennick. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University
Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd. 1933, 1989.
(Accessed from http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0052%3Abook
%3D5%3Asection%3D1013a)
Ouch. I lost a substantial number of comments - hopefully the recapitulated version will have merits.
ReplyDeleteAs you recognize by referencing it yourself, the ready slippage between problems in mimesis/diegesis and epistemology is problematic. The problems in mimesis/diegesis are relatively transparent: representing the whale is a struggle for perfectly obvious reasons, a struggle for all who try to represent it in different forms.
Obviously, to know and to represent are somewhat different. To approach knowledge as such through Aristotle is fine - but is oddly unjustified. I think your discussion of the four causes is interesting, but there's no whisper of evidence that either Melville or you find Aristotelian epistemology compelling. It's still a good lens through which to look, but the rigor of your analysis is totally out of proportion to the absence of any rigor at all when chosing to use the approach.
The discussion of final causes in terms of science is interesting, but it also demands that you widen your focus. Think of the chapter on fossil whales, for instance; think of the gnostic meditations; think of the moment when we drop into the perspective of the whale himself. This is a rich set of thoughts on MD, but weakened by its relative lack of attention to the text.
Question: are you confident that Ishmael - I mean the final Ishmael, the one writing after the fact - does not have all four causes in mind? He imagines evolution shaping the whale (efficient); he imagines the uses, divine and prosaic, to which the whale is put (final); he elaborates on its structure, both presently and historically (formal) as well as the materials from which its is made (material). I think you give Ishmael-as-narrator too little credit here. Remember, he thinks in terms of Kant, Plato, Locke, etc. For this argument, you *need* to engage with the the narrator.
Question: Is Darwinian evolution positivist? Wilson would say yes. Lewontin would say no - or at least that it ought not to be, and very possibly that Darwin didn't frame it as such.
Your claim that the narrator must be separated from Ishmael is deeply relevant to your argument. We agree on that - so why don't you present the argument for the separation? (I'd argue that they are both Ishmael at different stages of development, including epistemological development).
For what it's worth, I have had a lot to see in the past about my own anti-teleological reading of Moby-Dick. Nobody should deny your point that the whale does bring a kind of end, a telos - and yet, the end is not an end. Ishmael continues! He learns and retells the Town-Ho's story, he explores the south pacific, etc. My past argument has basically been that we must be wary of confusing death (thanotos) with a final cause (telos), though we have our reasons for conflating them.
Regardless of our disagreements - this has been a thoroughly enjoyable theorization of MD, with one glaring problem.
We don't know why you have allegiance to Aristotle. This is profoundly important, but you're completely silent on it. Your theory has an origin, and needs at least brief explanation.
Your slow to really get going, and often disengaged from relevant details of the text (much as I love this - how do you manage to ignore the Town-Ho's story, for instance?). How to free up the space to spend more time on the absent details? Begin faster!
My candidate? Begin, roughly, with "the whale in 1851." Not that everything before needs to be cut - it would just help you greatly to reorient the essay around your actual reading, and to figure out what supplementary material you really need, when all is said and done.